Another Effort to Void Our Basic Rights
Tibor R. Machan*
In this short essay I address an argument concerning welfare
rights made against the late Robert Nozick by Adrian Bardon a while
back.[i]
Bardon
brings up an issue that’s central concerning the nature of basic
individual rights that the American founders proposed as the foundations
of a constitutional government (and were, in fact, partly incorporated
and elaborated in the Bill of Rights).
Bardon argues that he has successfully “cast doubt on that
approach to rights” that holds that “there are negative rights that
cannot be outweighed.”[ii]
Interestingly there is no need to go much further since Bardon’s way of
putting his point already shows how wide off the mark he is concerning
an essential feature or nature of rights. Specifically, individual
rights, the unalienable sort the Declaration lists, aren’t like other
good things—such as ice skating, volleyball, dinner at home or at a
restaurant, a vacation in Hawaii or one in Italy—which may be weighed
and compared. It’s a category mistake to think they are, not unlike
thinking that one can weigh seconds or that fingers can think about
something.
Consider a very widely accepted right, that of a woman to be
free of rape. What would it mean to have such a right outweighed?
Bardon’s conception of such a basic right raises the possibility that
someone might weigh it against, say, a desperate male’s desire to gain
sexual satisfaction by using her against her will. But this is quite
out of the question—the two are incomparable, incommensurate. The right
to be free is a principle—a firm limit or a basic standard of just
conduct if you will—which identifies the fact that women are free to do
as they choose involving their own bodies, that they are sovereign
authorities concerning how to live their sex lives, regarding to whom
they will give their consent to engage in sex, etc.[iii]
Of course, Bardon is concerned with property rights but he forgets
that these, too, are rights to action, not rights to objects. As Ayn
Rand makes clear, “the right to property is a right to action, like all
the others: it is not the right to an object, but to the action and the consequences of producing or earning that object. It is not a guarantee that a man will earn any property,
but only a guarantee that he will own it if he earns it. It is the
right to gain, to keep, to use and to dispose of material values.”[iv]
Put another way, the right to private property is a right to acquire and to hold—which are both actions—various items
no one has previously acquired and is holding—or ones others who have
acquired them and are holding are willing, freely, to part with (another
action).
So, in fact, private property rights are akin to rights to act
freely—as when one acts to engage in consensual sex or work or
recreation. In the case of property rights, one acts to engage in, as it
were, consensual acquisition or holding of some items. (Notice, no one
may impose ownership on another against his or her consent because of
this right to freedom of actions such as acquisition and holding.)
Thus, property rights identify someone’s sphere or range of freedom
of action vis-à-vis items in the world, not unlike the manner in which
the right to freedom of speech spells out spheres of freedom of action
vis-à-vis verbal or written expression of ideas. Indeed, these latter
presuppose the right to private property, for speeches need to be given someplace
to which one has a right or gained permission from those who do, and
writing takes places on materials (paper, blackboards, sand, computers,
etc.)
Now it is true that others could well desperately need the
items someone has come to own by exercising the right to acquisition and
holding but since that exercise may not be interfered with and
interference with it would place others in the position of violating the
agent’s basic rights—that is, sovereignty—consent needs to be secured
in order to obtain even such desperately needed items. A need cannot be
weighed against a right, anymore than a wish or desire or urgent want
can be weighed against a right.
There can be no weighing involved, not between rights, nor
between rights and needs, etc., although a rights holder could very well
weigh whether to hang on to what he or she owns, contribute it to the
person in dire need, to some cause or project, or otherwise dispose of
it in light of his or her weighing of the importance of these
alternative possibilities. The weighing is not of different rights or
different people’s rights but of the importance or value of the goals to
which one may contribute what one has the right to freely acquire.
Here is what would happen if the weighing were about rights. Someone would have to do the weighing.
By what right would such a person weigh other people’s rights? Would
that person’s right to weigh also be open to being weighed? By whom? The
whole process would amount to a conceptual and public policy mess.
In fact, the role—or conceptual point—of basic individual
rights is to remove from public policy, based on constitutional laws
that rest on rights, the element of arbitrariness by basing decisions on
self-consistent, compossible principles—that is, on the rule of
law—instead. The very conceptual point of rights within the sphere of
social, political and legal policy is lost if they are subject to being
weighed since they are supposed to be the rock bottom of public policy
decision making—if I have a right to do X, this is the end of the
story—none may act against me as I do X.
There is no such thing as “weighing rights”—the idea is what
philosophers call a category mistake, akin to talk about weighing, say,
time or concepts. Indeed, to even consider weighing rights is to suggest
that the importance of human beings, vis-à-vis their place in the
citizenry, may be weighed against each other within the realm of
politics, something that had been abandoned once the idea of inherent
status was jettisoned, finally, so no one could justly claim to be more
important than someone else as far as the law of the land is concerned.
* Tibor Machan is the R. C. Hoiles Professor of Business Ethics & Free Enterprise at the Argyros School of Business & Economics, Chapman University, Orange, CA 92866.
2 comments:
Post a Comment