Machan’s Archives: A Note on
Socialism as Elitism*
Tibor R. Machan
Since ancient times some people
have considered the market place an unruly forum in which to determine whose
work and what commodities are worth how much. With Marxism this view acquired a
pseudo-scientific status. The complaint that when free individuals and groups
exchange goods and services some will get more for their contributions than
they deserve reaches the level of a total ideology.
Before this complaint and its
ideological expression are dismissed, it is important to understand their appeal.
It isn’t very difficult to empathize with the complaint when we restrict it to
individual instances. Most people have experienced a feeling of dismay with
what certain producers in the market receive for their work. The pop music
groups make millions of dollars for grinding out a few pleasant but clearly not
phenomenal songs. A boxer gets millions of dollars for going eight or so rounds
before knocking out his opponent. A television commentator collects some
$200,000 a year for uttering two minutes worth of banalities twice or three
times a week for about half the season. A New
York Times columnist makes a bundle from writing flawed economic
commentaries! Surely these folks are not
worth all that money – or so the thought occurs to some of us. Especially when
others, who make far more worthy contributions, receive far more modest remunerations
for their efforts.
These sorts of considerations are
natural, even if not fully justified in the total context. We cannot deny that
monetarily speaking the worth of many a product and producer is in some sense
over or under estimated. Out of this impression, natural enough in individual
instances, grows a very dangerous ideological perspective. But one must
appreciate that some of the individual instances make sense.
Now really—what foolishness prompts
people to pay that kind of money for such frivolous results or charge so little
for the same? And it is not unreasonable, now and then, to question the wisdom
of various people when they do shell out enormous sums of money for goods or
services while other, quite objectively more worthwhile products (even to them
individually) could have been purchased for a more sensible price and some sell
something quite worthwhile for but a nominal price.
From these impressions the jump is
made, by Marxists and other statists that something must be done to stop such alleged
miscalculations. And then, very quickly, the suggestion is made that if only
some wise folks could make sure that the objective value of work and products
is identified, matters could be remedied in a jiffy.
Since, however, persuasion does not
guarantee results—people can ignore the advice of the wisest of men – the
appeal to coercion is readily welcome. The conclusion to this effect is highly
questionable—indeed, an out and out non-sequitor—admittedly. But as with all
questionable hypotheses, the ground from which they stem is usually firm
enough. Otherwise generally sensible human beings would never pick up on the
broader theory advanced. It helps to recall this when we want to understand why
so many people are sympathetic toward socialist/egalitarian political measures
and doctrine.
Yet understanding the ground for
the sympathy does not lead a rational person to accepting the broader inferences
drawn. There is one particularly odious implication that follows from what is
inferred from these understandable impressions. Others may be found as well,
but this one will pinpoint a clear-cut inconsistency in the broader picture
advanced by socialists.
The complaint begins by noting that
free people tend at times to overrate the work and products of their fellows.
True enough, they do. (There are advocates of the free market who would deny
this on grounds that no objective values exist. But this is self-defeating,
since they also hold that the free market is of objective value to us.) The
suggestion advanced in turn is that we should have a central governing body of
people who will make certain that such mistakes do not happen—even if it takes
the use of firing squads to accomplish this noble result. Yet if the premise is
true—that people make mistakes by over and underrating others’ work and
products—then the conclusion cannot follow—that people will make certain that
such mistakes do not happen. This is
because what people will do is tied
to what they can do. The body of
select people is no less a body of people than the body of people that makes up
the free market place!
Here is where the odious
implications of the broader picture emerge. We are asked to believe that some
people are inherently different from the rest of us. We are told that the select group—the leaders
of socialist/egalitarian governments via their schemes of distribution and
equalization—is immune from the errors of the rest of us. That the likes of Ralph
Nader, Chuck Schumer, Joe Biden, et al., are really inherently better and wiser
folk than are we all is what the citizenry is supposed to accept!
The conclusion is interesting.
Because starting from a desire for equality—fair pricing, lessening the
frequency of over- and underestimation of work, etc. – we are led to the
establishment of public policies that grant some people the legalized position
of institutionalizing their (elitist) errors. It is this conclusion that is
never justified. It is the view that this select group of individuals can and
will do better than free people in voluntary association at determining what is
good or bad within the realm of production and exchange.
The simple fact is—known since the
time of Thomas Aquinas—that we are best off taking the risk with the free
market. The “utopian vision” of perfect judgments needs to be abandoned. We
should all try to implement the best judgments we can make, at least within our own market
activities, and maybe even in cases where our help is asked for or freely
accepted.
It is futile to argue that market
decisions could not be better than they are. But it is far sillier to hold that
institutionalizing the will of some of us can produce a guaranteed utopia. In
that path lies disaster—and we are now tasting its beginnings in our own land.
*Published in The
Intercollegiate Review, Fall, 1975, pp. 33-34.
No comments:
Post a Comment